Skip to main content

Verified by Psychology Today

Neuroscience

Experiencing Art: It's a Whole-Brain Issue, Stupid!

In the brain of the beholder

We love art. We put it on our walls, we admire it at museums and on others' walls, and if we're inspired, we may even create it. Philosophers, historians, critics, and scientists have bandied about the reasons why we enjoy creating and beholding art, and each has offered important and interesting perspectives. Recently, brain scientists have joined the conversation, as it is now possible to put someone in a MRI scanner and assess brain activity in response to viewing art or even creating it (e.g., jazz improvisation). With such exciting new prospects, budding intellectual fields such as "neuroaesthetics," "neuroarthistory," and "neurocinematics" have cropped up.

I applaud these attempts to integrate science with the humanities. In the end, art is an experience, and as such neuroscience may be useful in explaining the biological processes underlying it. One feature that is often ignored, however, is the role that knowledge plays. We never experience art with naïve eyes. Rather we bring with us a set of preconceived notions in the form of our cultural background, personal knowledge, and even knowledge about art itself. In large measure, what we like is based on what we know. When we accept the fact that our art experience depends on a confluence of sensations, knowledge, and feelings, it becomes clear that there is no "art center" in the brain. Instead, when we confront art, we essentially co-opt the multitude of brain regions we use in everyday interactions with the world. Thus, with respect to "neuroaesthetics," the question, "How do we experience art?" can be simply answered as, "It's a whole-brain issue, stupid!"

We can, however, go further in developing a science of aesthetics, as the brain is not a homogenous blob of neurons. Different regions serve different functions, and over the past two decades, neuroimaging research has advanced our understanding of the biological bases of many mental functions, to the point that it has completely revolutionized psychological science. What has become clear is that for a thorough analysis of any complex mental process, including the appreciation of art, we must characterize how neural processes interact in addition to where in the brain they occur. As a jumpstart toward analyzing our art experience, I have proposed a simple framework I call the I-SKE model, which represents essential components of our response to art: the intention (I) of an artist to offer an artwork, and three psychological components of the beholder: sensation (S), knowledge (K), and emotion (E).

The I-SKE Framework

I contend that as beholders we must consider how an artwork stimulates our senses, how it makes us think (i.e., conceptual knowledge), and how it drives emotions. When all three are at their extreme—11 on a scale of 10—we generate that "wow" feeling, as one might experience when confronted with Michelangelo's David or Van Gogh's Starry Night Over the Rhone.

On a recent visit to Paris, I had several "wow" moments at the Jeu de Paume gallery where a retrospective of Lorna Simpson works is being held. I was familiar with Simpson's photographic works, though primarily through book reproductions. At the exhibition, her photographs come alive as they are large and lusciously detailed. They are intensely moving and force you to ponder about their meaning. Even more provocative were her video installations, particularly Cloudscape, 2004, in which a man stands and whistles a haunting melody while an ethereal haze blows around him. Half way through the video, the scene shifts subtly, which makes one consider the conceptual underpinnings of the work. I won't reveal the nature of the change, but one can view it at Lorna Simpson's website.

Cloudspace, Lorna Simpson

Whenever we experience a work of art, we must consider how it stimulates our sensations, thoughts, and feelings. Yet you might ask, can the firing of neurons really tell us about the way we appreciate a Leonardo, Picasso, or Simpson? Do we even know what an "art" experience is? There are certainly limits to current brain imaging technology, and there may even be inherent limits in the degree to which science can contribute to our understanding of art and aesthetics. Indeed, there is a backlash to the growing interest in applying brain imaging to just about anything—from looking at art to deciding which soda you like—as scientists and the popular press have often exaggerated the findings (see Neuromania, Oxford University Press). Flashy brain images seen in print and on the web make it easy to fall prey to a modern-day version of phrenology in which bright spots on a brain scan are used to define complex mental functions. Yet by considering a multidisciplinary approach that fosters interactions among philosophers, historians, scientists, and artists themselves, we may be able to gain a better understanding of the joy of art. In addition, by evaluating such a universal and distinctly human practice, art may tell us more about brain than the other way around.

advertisement
More from Arthur P. Shimamura Ph.D.
More from Psychology Today
More from Arthur P. Shimamura Ph.D.
More from Psychology Today